Adam Smith and his disciples today see markets working as if they were guided by a beneficent, invisible hand, allocating scarce productive resources and distributing goods and services efficiently. Critics, on the other hand, see markets working as if they were guided by a malevolent, invisible foot, misrepresenting people's preferences and misallocating resources. After explaining the basic laws of supply and demand on which economists of all stripes more or less agree, this chapter explains the logic behind these opposing views and points out what determines where the truth lies.
If we leave decisions to the market about how much to produce, how to produce it, and how to distribute it, what will happen? Only after we know what markets will do can we decide if they are leading us to do what we would want to, or misleading us to do things we should not want to do.
What is a market?
A market is a social institution in which participants can exchange a good or service with one another on terms they find mutually agreeable. It is part of the institutional boundary of society located in the economic sphere of social life. If a good is exchanged in a "free" market, anyone can play the role of seller by agreeing to provide the good for a particular amount of money. And anyone can play the role of buyer by agreeing to purchase the good for a particular amount of money. The market for the good consists of all the potential buyers and sellers. Our analysis of the market consists of examining all the potential deals these buyers and sellers would be willing to make and predicting which deals will occur and which ones will not. We do this by using four "laws" concerning supply and demand.
The "law" of supply
The first "law" we use to analyze a market is called the law of supply which states that in most markets we expect the number of units of the good suppliers will offer to sell to increase if the price they receive for the good increases. There are two reasons for this: (1) At higher prices there are likely to be more suppliers. That is, at a low price some potential suppliers may choose not to play the role of seller at all, but at a higher price they may decide it is worth their while to "enter the market." So, at higher prices we might have a greater number of individual suppliers. (2) Individual suppliers who were already selling a certain quantity at the lower price may wish to sell more units at the higher price. If the individual seller produces the good under conditions of rising cost - i.e. the more units they produce the more it costs to produce another unit - a higher price means they can produce more units whose cost will be covered by their selling price. Or, if the seller has a fixed amount of the good in hand they may be induced to part with a larger portion of it once the price is higher. In any case, the "law of supply" tells us to expect the quantity of a good potential suppliers will be willing to supply to be a positive function of price.
The "law" of demand
The second "law" is the law of demand which states that in most markets we expect the number of units of the good demanders will
offer to buy to decrease if the price they have to pay increases. There are two reasons for, this as well: (1) At the higher price some
who had been buying before may become unable or unwilling to buy any of the good at all; and may therefore "drop out of the market."
So at higher prices we may have a smaller number of individual demanders. (2) Individual demanders who continue to buy may wish to
buy fewer units at the higher price than they did at the lower price. If the usefulness of the good to a buyer decreases the more units
they already have, the number of units whose usefulness outweighs the price the buyer must pay will decrease the higher the price. So
the "law of demand" tells us to expect the quantity of a good potential buyers will be willing to buy to be a negative function of price.
It
is important to understand that these so-called "laws" should not be interpreted like the laws of physics. No economist believes the
demand of every individual demander in every market decreases as market price rises, or that the amount every seller offers to supply in
every market increases as market price rises. In other words, economists recognize that individuals may well "disobey" the "laws" of
supply and demand. Moreover, there may be whole markets that disobey these laws at particular times, so that market supply fails to
rise, or market demand fails to fall when market price rises. Markets for stocks and markets for currencies, for example, ,display
annoying propensities to violate the "law of supply" and "law of demand."
A rise in the price of Amazon.com stock can unleash a rush
of new buyers who demand more of the stock anticipating further increases in price, and can shrink the supply of sellers who become
even more reluctant to part with Arnnazon. com while its price is increasing. The "laws" of supply and demand certainly do little to help
us understand stock market "bubbles." In 1997 a drop in the price of Thailand's currency, the bhat, triggered the Asian financial crisis when buyers disappeared from the market afraid to buy bhat while its price was falling, and sellers flooded the market hoping to
unload their bhat before it fell even farther in value. Clearly the "laws" of supply and demand are not going to help us understand
the logic behind currency crises. We will take up these
"annoying" anomalies when market participants interpret changes in market signals about what direction a price is moving in when we examine disequilibrating forces than can operate in markets
later in this chapter. But for now it is sufficient to note that the "laws" of supply and demand should be interpreted simply as plausible
hypotheses about the behavior of buyers and sellers in many markets under many conditions.
At this point economists invariably use a simple graph to illustrate the laws of supply and demand. We plot market price on a vertical axis
and the quantity or number of units all potential suppliers, in sum total, would be willing to supply in a specified time period on the
horizontal axis. According to the law of supply as we go up the vertical axis, at ever higher prices, the number of units all potential
suppliers would be willing to supply in a given time period, or the "market supply," increases. This gives us an upward sloping market
supply curve, or in different words a market supply curve with a positive slope. Similarly, we plot market price on a vertical axis and the
quantity, or number of units all potential demanders, in sum total, would be willing to buy in a given time period on the horizontal axis.
According to the law of demand as we go up the vertical axis, at ever higher prices, the number of units all potential demanders would
be willing to buy, or the "market demand," decreases. This gives us a downward sloping market demand curve, or in different words, a
market demand curve with a negative slope. While these are logically two separate graphs illustrating two different "laws" or functional
relationships, since the vertical axis is the same in both cases, and the horizontal axis is measured in units of the same good supplied or
demanded in the same time period, we can combine the two graphs into one with an upward sloping market supply curve and a
downward sloping market demand curve. In this most familiar of all graphs in economics one must remember: (1) the independent
variable is price, and this is measured (unconventionally) on the vertical axis, while the dependent variable, quantity supplied or
demanded by market participants, is measured (unconventionally) on the horizontal axis. (2) When using the market supply curve the
horizontal axis measures the number of units of the good all potential suppliers would be willing to sell at different prices. (3) When
using the market demand curve the horizontal axis measures the number of units of th good all potential demanders would be willing to
buy at different prices. (4) There is an implicit time period buried in the units of measurement on the horizontal axis. For example, the
supply and demand curves and the graph will look different if the horizontal axis is measured in bushels of apples supplied and
demanded per week than if it is measured in bushels of apples supplied and demanded per month.
The "law" of uniform price
The law of uniform price all units of a good in a market will sell at the same price no matter who are the buyers and sellers.llers.
This might seem surprising since some of the deals struck will be between high cost producers and buyers who are very desirous of the
good, and some of the deals will be struck between low cost producers and buyers who are lukewarm about buying at all. Nonetheless,
the law of uniform price says a good will tend to sell at the same price no matter who the seller and buyer may be. The logic of this law
can be illustrated by asking what would happen if some buyers and sellers were arranging deals at a lower price than others for the same
good. In this case it would pay for anyone to enter the part of the market where the good was selling at the lower price as a buyer and
buy up all they could, and then enter the part of the market where deals were being struck at the higher price as a seller to re-sell at a
profit. This activity is called "arbitrage," and in a free market where any who wish can participate as buyers or sellers the activity of
arbitrage should drive all deals to be struck at the same price. Where prices are lower arbitrage increases demand and raises price, and
where prices are higher arbitrage increases supply and lowers price - driving divergent prices for the same good in a market closer
together. Of course, this assumes that "a rose is a rose is a rose is a rose" in the words of one of the great French literati, Gertrude Stein
- that is, that there are no qualitative differences between different units of the good. But subject to this assumption, and the energy levels
of those who would profit from doing nothing other than buying "cheap" and selling "dear," economists expect all units of a good that is
bought and sold in a "well ordered" market to sell more or less at the same price.
The micro "law" of supply and demand
I call the third "law" the micro law of supply and demand to distinguish it from a different law we study in chapter 6 that I call the "macro law of supply and demand." The micro law of supply and demand states that in a free market the uniform market price will adjust
until the number units buyers want to buy is equal to the numberof units sellers want to sell. In terms of the supply and
demand graph in Figure 4. 1, the micro law of supply and demand says that the market will settle at the price across from
where the market supply and demand curves cross, and at the quantity bought and sold beneath where the supply and
demand curves cross. This price and this quantity bought and sold are called the equilibrium price and equilibrium quantity,
so another way of stating the micro law of supply and demand is: markets will settle at their equilibrium prices, and if left to
the free market the quantity of any good that will be produced and consumed will be the equilibrium quantity.
The rationale for the micro law of supply and demand is as follows: Suppose the going market price, P(l), is higher than the equilibrium price, P(e). In this case if we read across from this price to find out how much buyers are willing to buy, Qd(l), as compared to how much suppliers are willing to sell, Qs(1), we discover from the market demand curve and market supply curve that buyers are not willing to buy all that sellers are willing to sell at this price, Qd(l) < Qs(l). In other words, at this price there will be excess supply in the market for the good. What can we expect sellers to do? In conditions of excess supply sellers fall into two groups: those who are happily succeeding in selling their goods at P(I) and those who cannot sell all they want and are therefore frustrated. Those who are not able to sell their goods have an incentive to lower their asking price below the going market price in order to move from the group of frustrated sellers to the group of successful sellers, thereby driving the market price down in the direction of the equilibrium price. Buyers also have an incentive to only agree to buy at a price below the going market price when they notice there is excess supply in the market since they know that there are some frustrated sellers out there who should be willing to accept less than the going market price, providing another reason why market price should start to fall in the direction of the equilibrium price.
On the other hand, suppose the going market price, P(2), is lower than the equilibrium price, P(e). If we read across from this price to find out how much buyers are willing to buy, Qd(2), as compared to how much suppliers are willing to sell, Qs(2), we discover from the market demand curve and market supply curve that sellers are not willing to sell all that buyers are willing to buy at this price, Qs(2) > Qd(2). In other words, at this price there will be excess demand in the market for the good. What can we expect buyers to do? In conditions of excess demand buyers fall into two groups: those who are happily able to buy all the good they want at P(2), and those who are not able to buy all they want and are therefore frustrated. Those who are not able to buy all they want have an incentive to raise their offer price above the going market price in order to move from the group of frustrated buyers to the group of successful buyers, thereby driving the market price up in the direction of the equilibrium price. Sellers also have an incentive to only agree to sell at a price above the going market price when they notice there is excess demand in the market since they know that there are some frustrated buyers who should be willing to pay more than the going market price, providing another reason why market price should rise in the direction of the equilibrium price.
So for actual market prices above the equilibrium price there are incentives for frustrated sellers to cut their asking price and buyers to offer a lower price, driving the market price down toward the equilibrium price. And as the market price drops the amount of the excess supply will decrease since the law of supply says that supply decreases as price falls and the law of demand says that demand increases as price falls. And for market prices below the equilibrium price there are incentives for frustrated buyers to raise their offer price and for sellers to raise their asking price, driving the market price up toward the equilibrium price. And as the market price rises the excess demand will decrease since the law of demand says that demand decreases as price rises, and the law of supply says that supply increases as price rises. So according to the micro law of supply and demand, the only stable price will be the equilibrium price because self-interested behavior of frustrated sellers or buyers will lead to changes in price under conditions of both excess supply and excess demand, and only at the equilibrium price is there neither excess supply nor excess demand. This particular kind of selfinterested behavior of. buyers and sellers - individually rational responses to finding oneself unable to sell or buy all one wants at the going market price - can be thought of as "equilibrating forces" that economists expect to operate in markets. So the micro law of supply and demand can be thought of as a "law" explaining why there should be equilibrating forces at work in markets. We will discover below that market enthusiasts and critics disagree about how strong these "equilibrating forces" are compared to "disequilibrating forces" the micro law of supply and demand does not alert us to that sometimes operate alongside equilibrating forces.
There are a few things worth noting at this point:
1.There are different senses in which buyers or sellers are "satisfied." All buyers would always like to pay a lower price, and all sellers would
always like to receive a higher price. So in that sense, neither buyers nor sellers are ever "satisfied" no matter what the going price. But when
the market price is above the equilibrium price, while successful sellers will be pleased, there will be unsuccessful sellers who will be
displeased. Moreover, there is something the non-sellers can do about their frustrations: they can offer to sell at a lower price. Similarly,
when the market price is below the equilibrium price, while successful buyers will be pleased, there will be unsuccessful buyers who will be
displeased. And what the non-buyers can do about their frustrations is to offer to pay a higher price.
2. It is always the case that the quantity bought will be equal to the quantity sold - whether the market is in equilibrium or not. This follows
because every unit that was bought was sold and every unit that was sold was bought! But that is not the same as saying that the quantity
demanders want to buy is equal to the quantity suppliers want to sell. There is only one price at which the quantity demanded will equal the
quantity supplied - the equilibrium price. At all other prices there will be either excess supply or excess demand. 3. Since not all markets are always in equilibrium, how much will be bought and sold when a market is out of equilibrium? This is where the
assumption of non-coercion in our definition of a market enters in: buyers cannot be forced to buy if they don't want to and sellers can't be
forced to sell if they don't want to. Wheti there is excess supply the sellers would like to sell more than~ the buyers want to buy at the going
price. So under conditions of excess supply it is the buyers who have the upper hand, in a sense, and they will determine how much is going
to be bought, and therefore sold. In Figure 4.1 when market price is P(1) and there is excess supply buyers will only buy Qd(1) and
therefore, that is all sellers, will be able to sell. When there is excess demand the buyers would like to buy more than the sellers want to sell.
So under conditions of excess demand it is the sellers who have the upper hand and will determine how much is going to be sold, and
therefore bought. In Figure 4.1 when market price is P(2) and there is excess demand sellers will only sell Qs(2) and therefore, that is all
buyers will be able to buy. Elasticity of supply and demand
The law of demand just says that as price rises we expect the quantity demanded to fall. It doesn't say whether demand will fall a lot or a little. If
a I% increase in price leads to more than a 1 % fall in quantity demanded, we say that market demand is elastic. If a 1 % increase in price
leads to less than a 1% fall in quantity demanded, we say that market demand is inelastic. Similarly, the law of supply just says that as price
rises we expect the quantity supplied to rise; it doesn't say whether supply will rise a lot or a little. If a 1% increase in price leads to more than a
1% rise in quantity supplied, we say that market supply is elastic. If a 1% increase in price leads to less than a 1% rise in quantity supplied, we
say that market supply is inelastic. You can use your understanding of elasticity to predict whether more or less unemployment will result from minimum wage laws, and
whether more or fewer shortages will result from price controls. Draw a labor market diagram with one "flat" (elastic) labor demand curve and
one "steep" (inelastic) labor demand curve where both demand curves cross the labor supply curve at the same point. Where both demand
curves cross the supply curve determines the equilibrium wage rate and the equilibrium level of employment. Now draw in a minimum wage
above the equilibrium wage and see what happens to employment as buyers (employers) determine the quantity that will be bought and sold in a
market with excess supply. Notice that the drop in employment is greater if the demand for labor is more elastic, and smaller if the demand for
labor is more inelastic. Draw a diagram for the steel market with one "flat" or elastic supply curve and one "steep" or inelastic supply curve
where both supply curves cross the demand curve for steel at the same point. Where both supply curves cross the demand curve determines the
equilibrium price of steel and the equilibrium quantity of steel production. Now draw a price ceiling below the equilibrium price and see what
happens to production when suppliers determine the amount that will be sold and bought in a market with excess demand. Notice that the drop
in production and shortage is greater if the supply of steel is more elastic and smaller if the supply of steel is more inelastic. The principal factors that determine the elasticity of market demand are the availability and closeness of substitutes for the good, and the
organization and bargaining power of potential buyers. The principal factors that determine the elasticity of market supply are the mobility of
productive factors into and out of the industry and the organization and bargaining power of potential sellers. Adam Smith noticed something strange but wonderful about free, markets. He saw competitive markets as a kind of beneficent, "invisible hand"
that guided "the private interests and passions of men" in the direction "which is most agreeable to the interest of the whole society." Smith
expressed this view, in perhaps the most widely~,quoted passage in all of economics in The Wealth of Nations published in 1776: Every
individual necessarily labours to render the annual revenue of the society as great as he can. He generally, indeed, neither intends to
promote the public interest, nor knows how much he is promoting it. He intends only his own gain, and he is in this, as in many other
cases, led by an invisible hand to promote an end which was no part of his intention. Nor is it always the worse for the society that it was
no part of it. By pursuing his own interest he frequently promotes that of the society more effectually than when he really intends to
promote it ... It is not from the benevolence of the butcher, the brewer, or the baker that we expect our dinner, but from their regard to
their self-interest. We address ourselves, not to their humanity, but to their self-love, and never talk to them of our necessities, but of
their advantages. In the words of Robert Heilbroner: "Adam Smith's laws of the market are basically simple. They show us how the drive of individual self interest in an environment of similarly motivated individuals will result in competition; and they further demonstrate how competition will
result in the provision of those goods that society wants, in the quantities that society desires." 1 But how does this miracle happen? Suppose consumers' taste for apples increases and their taste for oranges decreases - for whatever reason. Assuming consumers know
best what they like, how would we want the economy to respond to this new situation? If there were an omniscient, beneficent God in
charge of the economy she would shift some of our scarce productive resources - land, labor, fertilizer, etc. - out of orange production
and into apple production. What would a system of free markets do? These changes in consumer tastes would shift the market demand
curve for apples out to the right indicating that consumers now would demand more apples at each and every price of apples than before,
and the market demand curve for oranges back to the left -indicating that consumers would now demand fewer oranges at each and
every price than before - leading to excess demand for apples and excess supply of oranges at their old equilibrium prices. The micro law
of supply and demand would drive the price of apples up until the excess demand for apples was eliminated and the price of oranges
down until the excess supply of oranges was eliminated. At the new higher price of apples, the law of supply tells us that former apple
growers, and any new ones drawn into the industry by the higher price of apples, would increase production of apples by purchasing
more land, labor, fertilizer, etc. At the new lower price of oranges the law of supply tells us that orange growers would decrease their
production of oranges by using less land, labor, and fertilizer, etc. to grow oranges. Bingo! As if guided by an invisible hand, without
anyone thinking or planning at all, the free market does what a beneficent God would have done for us! 1. Robert Heilbroner, The Worldly Philosophers (Simon and Schuster, 1992): 55. Or, suppose agronomists develop a new strain of apple that can be grown with less land between trees than before. This is a technical
change that reduces the amount of scarce productive resources it takes to grow apples compared to the past. An omniscient, beneficent
God would have consumers buy more apples and fewer oranges now that apples are less socially costly. What will free markets do? The
cost-reducing change in apple growing technology will shift the market supply curve for apples out to the right because now apple
growers can cover the cost of growing more apples than before at each and every price - producing an excess supply of apples at the old
equilibrium price. The micro law of supply and demand will lower apple prices until the excess supply is eliminated and we reach the new
equilibrium in the apple market. And the law of demand tells us that consumers will buy more apples at the lower price. Meanwhile, over
in the orange market, the fall in the price of apples leads some fruit buyers to substitute apples for oranges which shifts the demand curve
for oranges back to the left indicating that fewer oranges will be demanded at each and every price of oranges now that the price of
apples is lower - creating excess supply in the orange market. This will lead to a fall in the price of oranges and lower levels of orange
production. Bingo! The free market will bring about an increase in apple production and consumption and a decrease in orange
production and consumption when the social cost of producing apples decreases relative to the social cost of producing oranges - just
what we would have wanted to happen. We can combine Figure 2.2: The Efficiency Criterion (p. 33) and Figure 4.1: Supply and Demand (p. 73) to see what Smith's
conclusion that markets harness individually rational behavior to yield socilally rational outcomes amounts to. According to the micro
law of supply and demand, the market outcome will be the equilibrium outcome, and the number of apples produced and consumed can
be found directly below where the market supply curve crosses the market demand curve. According to the efficiency criterion the
optimal number of apples to produce and consume can be found directly below where the marginal social cost curve crosses the marginal
social benefit curve. So the market outcome will yield the socially efficient outcome if and only if the market supply curve coincides with
the MSC curve and the market demand curve coincides with the MSB curve. Another way to put it is that if and only if market supply
closely approximates marginal social cost and market demand closely approximates marginal social benefits will free market outcomes be
socially efficient outcomes. But do market supply and demand reasonably express marginal social costs and benefits? That is one way to see the debate between
those who see market allocations as being guided by an invisible hand versus those who see them as being misguided by an invisible foot.
If market supply and demand closely approximate true marginal social costs and benefits then the individually rational behavior of buyers
and sellers and the workings of the micro law of supply and demand would be working in the social interest because they would be
driving production and consumption of goods and services toward socially efficient levels. Moreover, whenever conditions changed
social costs or benefits these equilibrating forces would move us to the new socially efficient outcome. In other words, markets would
yield efficient allocations of scarce productive resources. On the other hand, if there are significant discrepancies between market supply
and marginal social costs and/or market demand and marginal social benefits, individually rational behavior of buyers and sellers and the
micro law of supply and demand work against the social interest by driving us to produce too little of some goods and too much of
others. In other words, by relying on market forces we would consistently get inefficient allocations of productive resources. Mainstream and political economists agree on one part of the answer before parting company. They agree that what market supply
captures and represents are the costs born by the actual sellers of goods and services; and what market demand represents are the
benefts enjoyed by the actual buyers of goods and services. We call these "private costs" and "private benefits." A rational buyer will
keep buying a good as long as the private benefit to her of an additional unit is at least as great as the price she must pay for it. In other
words, her marginal private benefit curve is her individual demand curve. Since the market demand curve is simply the summation of all
individual demand curves, the market demand curve is simply the sum of all marginal private benefit curves. A rational seller will keep
selling as long as the cost to her of producing another unit of output is no greater than the price she will get from selling it. In other
words, her marginal private cost curve is her individual supply curve. Since market supply is simply the summation of all individual
supply curves, the market supply curve is simply the sum of all marginal private cost curves. So the question becomes: When do private
costs and benefits differ from social costs and benefits? In fairness to Adam Smith, the distinction between private and social costs and benefits was not clear in his lifetime. Smith, and
"classical economists" who lived and wrote after him as well, conflated social and private costs and benefits and never asked if anyone
other than the seller bore part of the cost of increased production, or anyone other than the buyer enjoyed part of the benefit of increased
consumption of different kinds of goods and services. The modern terminology for differences between social and private costs of
production is "a production externality." And the name for the difference between social and private benefits from consumption is "a
consumption externality." These "external effects" can be negative if someone other than the seller suffers a cost associated with
production so social costs exceed private costs, or if someone other than the buyer is adversely affected by the buyer's consumption so
private benefits exceed social benefits. Or external effects can be positive if the private costs of production exceed the social costs or
social benefits of consumption exceed private benefits. Adam Smith's vision of the market as a mechanism that successfully harnesses
individual desires to the social purpose of using scarce productive resources efficiently hinges on the assumption that external effects are
insignificant. And, indeed, this is precisely the un-emphasized assumption that lies behind the mainstream conclusion that markets are
remarkable efficiency machines that require little social effort on our part. In fact, the mainstream view today is a strident echo of Adam
Smith's conclusion that the only "effort" required is the "effort" to resist the temptation to tamper with the free market place and simply:
"laissez faire." Mainstream economic theory teaches that the problem with externalities is that the buyer or seller has no incentive to take the external
cost or benefit for others into account when deciding how much of something to supply or demand. And Mainstream theory teaches that
the "problem" with public goods is that nobody can be excluded from benefitting from a public good once anyone buys it, and therefore
everyone has an incentive to "ride for free" on the purchases of others rather than revealing their true willingness to pay for public goods
by purchasing them in the market place. In other words, mainstream economics concedes that the laws of the market place will lead to
inefficient allocations of scarce productive resources when public goods and externalities come into play because important benefits or
costs go unaccounted for in the market decision making process. If anyone cares to listen, standard economic theory predicts that market
forces will lead us to produce too much of goods whose production and/or consumption entail negative externalities, too little of goods
whose production and/or consumption entail positive externalities, and much too little, if any, public goods. We can see the problem of
negative externalities by looking at the automobile industry, and the problem of public goods by considering pollution reduction. Externalities: the auto industry The micro law of supply and demand tells us how many cars will be produced and consumed if we leave the decision to the free market.
The price of cars will adjust until there is neither excess supply nor excess demand at which point the "equilibrium" number of cars will
be produced and consumed. The question is whether or not this is more, less, or the same number of cars that is socially efficient, or
optimal to produce and consume. As we saw, the socially efficient level of auto production and consumption is where the MSB curve
crosses the MSC curve. If the market supply curve for cars coincides with the MSC curve for cars, and if the market demand curve for
cars coincides with the MSB curve for cars, the market outcome will be the efficient outcome. Otherwise, it will not. Let us assume that the market supply curve for cars does a reasonably good job of approximating the marginal private costs the
makers and sellers of cars incur. That is, we will assume that if car manufacturers can get a price for a car that is something above what it
costs them to make it, they will produce and sell the car. In this case the market supply curve, S, closely approximates the marginal
private cost (MPC) curve for making cars: S = MPC. But if there are costs to external parties above and beyond the costs of inputs car
makers must pay for, there is no reason to expect the car makers to take them into account. So if the corporations making cars in Detroit
also pollute the air in ways that cause acid rain, the costs that take the form of lost benefits to those who own, use, or enjoy forests and
lakes in Eastern Canada and the United States will not be taken into account by those who make the decisions about how many cars to
produce. Nevertheless, along with the cost of steel, rubber and labor needed to make a car - which are costs borne by car manufacturers -
the costs of acid rain are part of the social costs of making cars even if they are not borne by car makers. To the cost of steel, rubber, and
labor that comprise the private costs of making a car, must be added the damage from acid rain that occurs when we make a car if we are
to have the full cost to society of making another car. In other words, the marginal social cost of making a car, MSC, is equal to the
marginal private cost of making the car, MPC, plus the marginal external costs associated with making the car, MEC: MSC = MPC +
MEC. Since MEC is positive for automobile production, marginal social cost always exceeds marginal private cost, which means the
marginal social cost curve for producing cars lies somewhere above the marginal private cost curve for making cars, which is, in turn,
roughly equal to the market supply curve for cars: MSC = MPC + MEC = S + MEC with MEC > 0. When car buyers consider whether or not to purchase a car they presumably compare the benefit they expect to get in the form of ease
and speed of transportation with the price they will have to pay out of their limited income. If the private benefit exceeds the price, they
will buy the car, and if it does not, they won't. This means the market demand curve, D, represents the marginal private benefit curve
from car consumption, MPB, reasonably well: D = MPB. But I am not the only person affected when I "consume" my car. When I drive
my car the exhausts add to the "greenhouse" gases in the atmosphere and contribute to global warming. When I drive from the suburbs
through inner city neighborhoods I contribute to urban smog, noise pollution, and congestion. In other words, when I consume a car
there are others who suffer negative benefits which means that the social benefit of consuming another car is less than the prIvate benefit
of consuming another car. So even if the market dernatid curve for cars reasonably represents the marginal private benefits of car
consumption, it overestimates the marginal social benefits of car consumption because it ignores the negative impact of car consumption
on those not driving them. The marginal social benefits from consuming another car, MSB, is equal to the marginal private benefits to the
car buyer plus the marginal external benefits to others, MEB: MSB = MPB + MEB. But in the case of car consumption the marginal
external "benefits," MEB, are negative. This implies that the marginal social benefit curve lies somewhere below the market demand
curve for automobiles: MSB = MPB, + MEB = D + MEB with MEB < 0.
But as can be seen in Figure 4.2, if the MSC curve lies above the market supply curve, and the MSB curve lies below the market
demand curve for cars, MSC and MSB will cross to the left of where the market supply and demand curves cross. Therefore the socially
efficient, or optimal level of automobile production (and consumption), A(O), will be less than the equilibrium level of production and
consumption, A(e), that the micro law of supply and demand will drive us toward. In other words, the market will lead us to produce and
consume more cars than is socially efficient, or optimal. The market will lead to too much car production and consumption because
sellers and buyers decide how many cars to produce and consume and they have no reason to take anything other than the costs and
benefits to them into account. They have no incentive to consider the external costs associated with producing and consuming cars. In
fact, they have good reason to ignore these external effects because taking them into account would make them individually worse off.
Not surprisingly we discover that if decision makers ignore negative consequences of doing something - in this case the negative external
effects of car production and consumption on people other than the car producer and buyer - they will decide to do too much of it - in
this case they will decide to produce and consume too many cars. 2
. ---------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
Public goods: pollution reduction A public good is a good produced by human economic activity that is consumed, to all intents and purposes, by everyone rather than
by an individual consumer. Unlike a private good such as underwear that affects only its wearer, public goods like pollution reduction
affect most people. In different terms, nobody can be excluded from " consuming" a public good - or benefitting from the existence of
the public good. This is not to say that everyone has the same preferences regarding public goods anymore than people have the same
preferences for private goods. I happen to prefer apples to oranges, and I value pollution reduction more than I value so-called "national
defense." There are others who place greater value on "national defense" than they do on pollution reduction, just as there are others
who prefer oranges to apples. But unlike the case of apples and oranges where those who prefer apples can buy more apples and those
who like oranges more can buy more oranges, all US citizens have to "consume" the same amount of federal spending on the military and
federal spending on pollution reduction. We cannot provide more military spending for the US citizens who value that public good more,
and more pollution reduction for the US citizens, who value the environment more. Whereas different Americans can consume different
amounts of private goods, we all must live in the same "public good world." What would happen if we left the decision about how much of our scarce productive resources to devote to producing public goods to
the free market? Markets only provide goods for which there is what we call "effective demand," that is, buyers willing and able to put
their money where their mouth is. But what incentive is there for a buyer to pay for a public good? First of all, no matter how much value
the public good, I only enjoy a tiny fraction of the overall, or social benefit that comes from having more of it since I cannot exclude
others who do not pay for it from benefitting as well. In different terms: Social rationality demands that an individual purchase a public
good up to the point where the cost of the last unit she purchased is as great as the benefits enjoyed by all who benefit, in sum total, from
her purchase of the good. But it is only rational for an individual to buy a public good up to the point where the cost of the last unit she
purchased is as great as the benefit she, herself, enjoys from the good. When individuals buy public goods in a free market they have no
incentive to take the benefits others enjoy into account when they decide how much to buy. Consequently they "demand" far less than is
socially efficient, if they purchase any at all. In sum, market demand will grossly under-represent the marginal social benefit of public
goods.
Another way to see the problem is to recognize that each potential buyer of a public good has an incentive to wait and hope that
someone else will buy the public good. A patient buyer can "ride for free" on others' purchases since non-payers cannot be excluded from
benefitting from public goods. But if everyone is waiting for someone else to plunk down their hard earned income for a public good,
nobody will demonstrate "effective demand" for public goods in the market place. "Free riding" is individually rational in the case of
public goods - but leads to an "effective demand" for public goods -that grossly underestimates their true social benefit. In chapter 5 we
explore this logic formally in "the public good game." What prevents a group of people who will benefit from a public good from banding together to express their demand for the good
collectively? The problem is that there is an incentive for people to lie about how much they benefit. If the associations of public good
consumers are voluntary, no matter how much I truly benefit from a public good, I am better off pretending I don't benefit at all. Then I
can decline membership in the association and avoid paying anything, knowing full well that I will, in fact, benefit from its existence
nonetheless. If the associations are not voluntary - i.e., if a government "drafts" people into the public good consuming coalition - there
is still an incentive for people to under-represent the degree to which they benefit if assessments are based on degree of benefit. This is
where the fact that not all people do benefit equally from different kinds of public goods becomes an important part of the problem. If we
knew that everyone truly valued a larger military to the same extent, there would be few objections to making everyone contribute the
same amount to pay for it. But there is every reason to believe this is not the case. In this context, if we believe that payments should be
related to the degree to which someone benefits, there is an incentive for everyone to pretend they benefit less than they do. If the
effective demand expressed by the nonvoluntary consuming coalition is based on these individually rational under-representations, it will
still significantly underrepresent the true social benefits people enjoy from the public good, and consequently lead to less demand for the
public good than is socially efficient, or optimal. In sum, because of what economists call the "free rider" incentive problem and the "transaction costs" of organizing and managing a
coalition of public good consumers, market demand predictably under-represents the true social benefits that come from consumption of
public goods. If the production of a public good entails no external effects so the market supply curve accurately represents the marginal
social costs of producing the public good, then since market demand will lie considerably under the true marginal social benefit curve for
the public good, the market equilibrium level of production and consumption will be significantly less than the socially efficient level. In
conclusion, if we left it to the free market and voluntary associations precious little, if any, of our scarce productive resources would be
used to produce public goods no matter how valuable they really were. As Robert Heilbroner put it: "The market has a keen ear for
private wants, but a deaf ear for public needs." The fact that pollution reduction is a public good has important implications for green consumerism in free market economies. There
are a number of cheap detergents that get my wash very white but cause considerable water pollution. "Green" detergents, on the other
hand, are more expensive and leave my whites more gray than white, but cause less water pollution. Whether or not I end up making the
socially responsible choice, because pollution reduction is a public good the market provides too little incentive for me to make the
socially efficient choice. My own best interests are served by weighing the disadvantage of the extra cost and grayer whites to me against
the advantage to me of the diminution in water pollution that would result if I use the green detergent. But presumably there are many
others besides me who also benefit from the cleaner water if I buy the green detergent - which is precisely why we think of "buying
green" as socially responsible behavior. Unfortunately the market provides no incentive for me to take their benefit into account. Worse
still, if I suspect others may consult only their own interests when they choose which detergent to buy, i.e., if I think they will ignore the
benefits to me and others if they choose the "green" detergent, by choosing to take their interests into account and consuming green
myself I risk not only making a choice that was detrimental to my own interests, I risk being played for a sucker as well. 3
This is not to say that many people will not choose to "do the right thing" and "consume green" in any case. Moreover, there may be
incentives other than the socially counterproductive market incentives that may overcome the market disincentive to consume green. The fact
that I am a member of the Southern Maryland Green Party and fear I would be ostracized if observed by a fellow party member with a polluting
detergent in my shopping basket in the check out line at the supermarket is apparently a powerful enough incentive in my own case to lead me to
buy a green detergent despite the market disincentive to do so. (Admittedly I have only a slight preference for white over gray clothes, and who
knows how long I will hold out if the price differential increases?) But the point is that because pollution reduction is a public good, market
incentives are perverse, i.e. lead people to consume less "green" and more "dirty" than is socially efficient. The extent to which people ignore the
perverse market incentives and act on the basis of concern for the environment, concern for others, including future generations, or in response
to non-market, social incentives such as fear of ostracism is important for the environment and the social interest, but does not make the market
incentives any the less perverse. 3. Most detergents call for a full cup per load of wash. Church & Dwight canceled a 1/4 cup laundry detergent product when consumer demand for this "green"
product proved insufficient. See Christine Canning, "The Laundry Detergent Market," in Household and Personal Products Industry, April 1996. The prevalence of external effects In face of these concessions - markets misallocate resources when there are externalities and public goods - how do market enthusiasts continue
to claim that markets allocate resources efficiently - as if guided by a beneficent invisible hand? The answer lies in an assumption that is explicit
in the theorems of graduate level micro economic theory texts but only implicit in undergraduate textbooks and in the advice of most
economists. The fundamental theorem of welfare economics states that if all markets are in equilibrium the economy will be in a Pareto
optimal state only if there are no external effects public goods. The assumption that there are no public goods or external effects is
explicit in the statement of the theorem that is the modern incarnation of Adam Smith's 200-year-old vision of an invisible hand - because
otherwise the theorem would be false! Since everyone knows there are externalities and public goods in the real world, the conclusion
that markets allocate resources reasonably efficiently in the real world rests on the assumption that external effects and public goods are
few and far between. This assumption is usually unstated, and its validity has never been demonstrated through empirical research. It is a
presumption implicit in an untested paradigm that lies behind mainstream economic theory - a paradigm that pretends that the choices
people make have little effect on the opportunities and well being of others. If we replace the implicit paradigm at the basis of mainstream economics with one that sees the world as a web of human interaction
where people's choices often have far reaching consequences for others, both now and in the future, the presumption that external effects
and public goods are the exception rather than the rule is reversed. Since political economists have long seen the world in just this way,
and everything we have learned about the relation between human choices and ecological systems over the past 30 years reinforces this
vision of interconnectedness, there is every reason for political economists to expect external and public effects to be the rule rather than
the exception. What is surprising is that- so few political economists have recognized the far reaching implication of their own beliefs
when it comes to assessing the efficiency of Markets. One stellar exception is EK Hunt. In an article "On Lemmings and Other
Acquisitive Animals" remarkable for its lack of impact on other political economists when published in June 1973 (Journal of Economic
Issues), EK Hunt stated the "reverse" assumption as follows:
The Achilles heel of welfare economics [as practiced by mainstream pro-market economists] is its treatment of externalities ... When
reference is made to externalities, one usually takes as a typical example an upwind factory that emits large quantities of sulfur oxides and
particulate matter inducing rising probabilities of emphysema, lung cancer, and other respiratory diseases to residents downwind, or a strip-mining
operation that leaves an irreparable aesthetic scar on the countryside. The fact is, however, that most of the millions of acts of production
and consumption in which we daily engage involve externalities. In a market economy any action of one individual or enterprise which
induces pleasure or pain to any other individual or enterprise ... constitutes an externality. Since the vast majority of productive and
consumptive acts are social, i.e., to some degree they involve more than one person, it follows that they will involve externalities. Our
table manners in a restaurant, the general appearance of our house, our yard or our person, our personal hygiene, the route we pick for a
joy ride, the time of day we mow our lawn, or nearly any one of the thousands of ordinary daily acts, all affect, to some degree, the
pleasures or happiness of others. The fact is ... externalities are totally pervasive ... Only the most extreme bourgeois individualism could
have resulted in an economic theory that assumed otherwise.
If the social effects of production and consumption frequently extend beyond the sellers and buyers of those goods and services, as
Hunt argues above, and if these external effects are not insignificant, markets will frequently misallocate resources leading us to produce
too much of some goods and too little of others. By ignoring negative external effects markets lead us to produce and consume more of
goods like automobiles than is socially efficient. By ignoring positive external effects markets lead us to consume less of goods like
tropical rain forests that recycle carbon dioxide and thereby reduce global warming than is socially efficient - instead we clear cut them or
burn them off to pasture cattle. And while markets provide reasonable opportunities for people to express their preferences for goods
and services that can be enjoyed individually with minimal "transaction costs," they do not provide efficient means for expressing desires
for goods that are enjoyed, or consumed socially, or collectively - like public space and pollution reduction. Markets create "free rider"
disincentives for those who would express their desires for public goods individually, and pose daunting transaction costs for those who
attempt to form a coalition of beneficiaries. In other words, markets have an anti-social bias. Worse still, markets provide powerful incentives for actors to take advantage of external effects in socially counterproductive ways,
and even to magnify or create new ones. Increasing the value of goods and services produced, and decreasing the unpleasantness of what
we have to do to get them, are two ways that producers can increase their profits in a market economy. And competitive pressures will
drive producers to do both. But maneuvering to appropriate a greater share of the goods and services produced by externalizing costs
and internalizing benefits without compensation are also ways to increase profits. Competitive pressures will drive producers to pursue
this route to greater profitability just as assiduously. Of course the problem is, while the first kind of behavior serves the social interest as
well as the private interests of producers, the second kind of behavior does not. Instead, when buyers or sellers promote their private
interests by externalizing costs onto those not party to the market exchange, or internalizing benefits without compensating external
parties, their "rent seeking behavior" introduces inefficiencies that lead to a misallocation of productive resources and consequently
decreases the value of all the goods and services produced. Questions market admirers seldom ask are: Where are firms most likely to
find the easiest opportunities to expand their profits? How easy is it to increase the quantity or quality of goods produced? How easy is it
to reduce the time or discomfort it takes to produce them? Alternatively, how easy is it to enlarge one's slice of the economic pie by
externalizing a cost, or by appropriating.A benefit without compensation? In sum, why should we assume that if it is infinitely easier to
expand profits by productive behavior than by rent seeking behavior? Yet this implicit assumption is what lie behind the view of markets
as efficiency machines. Market enthusiasts fail to notice that the same feature of market exchanges primarily responsible for small transaction costs -excluding
all affected parties but two from the transaction - is also a major source of potential gain for the buyer and seller. When the buyer and
seller of an automobile strike their convenient deal, the size of the benefit they have to divide between them is greatly enlarged by
externalizing the costs onto others of the acid rain produced by car production, and the costs of urban smog, noise pollution, traffic
congestion, and greenhouse gas emissions caused by car consumption. Those who pay these costs, and thereby enlarge car maker profits
and car consumer benefits, are "easy marks" for car sellers and buyers because they are geographically and chronologically dispersed, and
because the magnitude of the effect on each of them is small and unequal. Individually they have little incentive to insist on being party to
the transaction. Collectively they face transaction cost and free rider obstacles to forming a voluntary coalition to represent a large
number of people - each with little, but different, amounts at stake. Moreover, the opportunity for socially counterproductive rent seeking behavior is not eliminated by making markets perfectly competitive or entry costless, as is commonly assumed. Rent seeking at the expense of a buyer or seller may be eliminated by competitive
markets, i.e. the presence of innumerable sellers for buyers to choose from and innumerable buyers for sellers to choose from. But even if
there were, countless perfectly informed sellers and buyers in every market, even if the appearance of the slightest differences in average
profit rates in different industries induced instantaneous selfcorrecting entries and exits of firms, even if every market participant were
equally powerful and therefore equally powerless - in other words, even if we embrace the full fantasy of market enthusiasts -as long as
there are numerous external parties with small but unequal interests in market transactions, those external parties will face greater
transaction cost and free rider obstacles to a full and effective representation of their collective interest than any obstacles faced by the
buyer and seller in the exchange. And it is this unavoidable inequality that makes external parties easy prey to rent seeking behavior on
the part of buyers and sellers. Even if we could organize a market economy so that buyers and sellers never faced a more or less powerful
opponent in a market exchange, this would not change the fact that each of us has smaller interests at stake in many transactions in which
we are neither the buyer nor seller. Yet the sum total interest of all external parties can be considerable compared to the interests of the
buyer and the seller. It is the transaction cost and free rider problems of those with lesser interests that create an unavoidable inequality in
power, which, in turn, gives rise to the opportunity for individually profitable but socially counterproductive rent seeking on the part of
buyers and sellers in even the most competitive markets. A sufficient condition for buyers and sellers to profit in socially
counterproductive ways from maneuvering, rent seeking, or cost shifting behavior is that each one of us has diffuse interests that make us
affected external parties to many exchanges in which we are neither buyer nor seller - no matter how competitive markets may be. But socially counterproductive rent seeking behavior is not only engaged in at the expense of parties external to market exchanges. The real world
bears little resemblance to a game where all buyers and sellers are equally powerful, in which case it would be pointless for sellers or buyers to try to take
advantage of one another. In the real world it is often easier for powerful firms to increase profits by lowering the prices they pay less powerful suppliers
and raising the prices they charge powerless consumers than it is to search for ways to increase the quality of their products. In the real world there are
consumers with little information, time, or means to defend their interests. There are small, capital poor, innovative firms for giants like IBM and
Microsoft to buy up instead of tackling the hard work of innovation themselves. There are common property resources whose productivity can be
appropriated at little or no cost as they are overexploited at the expense of future generations. And finally, there is a government run by politicians whose
careers rely principally on their ability to raise campaign money, begging to be plied for tax dodges and corporate welfare programs financed at taxpayer
expense. In other words, in the real world where buyers and sellers are usually not equally powerful, the most effective profit maximizing strategy is
often to outmaneuver less powerful market opponents and expand one's slice of the pie at their expense rather than work to expand it. To the extent that consumer preferences are endogenous the degree of misallocation that results from uncorrected external effects in
market economies will increase, or "snowball" over time. As people adjust their preferences to the biases created by external effects in
the market price system, they will increase their preference and demand for goods whose production and/or consumption entails negative
external effects, but whose market prices fail to reflect these costs and are therefore lower than they should be; and they will decrease
their preference and demand for goods whose production and/or consumption entails positive external effects, but whose market prices
fail to reflect these benefits and are therefore higher than they should be. While this reaction, or adjustment, is individually rational it is
socially irrational and inefficient since it leads to even greater demand for the goods that market systems tend to overproduce, and even
less demand for the goods that market systems tend to underproduce. As people have greater opportunities to adjust over longer periods
of time, the degree of inefficiency in the economy will grow, or "snowball." 4 4. For a rigorous demonstration that endogenous preferences imply snowballing inefficiency when there are market externalities see theorems 7.1 and 7.2 in
Hahnel and Albert, Quiet Revolution in Welrare Economics. Market disequilibria Nobody knows where the equilibrium price in a market is. What the micro law of supply and demand says is that self-interested behavior
on the part of frustrated sellers when there is excess supply because the actual price is higher than the equilibrium price, and selfinterested
behavior on the part of frustrated buyers when there is excess demand because market price is below the equilibrium price, will tend to
move markets toward their equilibria. But as long as a market is out of equilibrium the quantity bought and sold will be less than the
quantity that would be bought and sold if the market were in equilibrium. Since the equilibrium quantity is the same as the socially
efficient quantity to produce and consume in absence of external effects, this means markets do not yield efficient outcomes when they
are out of equilibrium even in absence of external effects. So the first problem is the slower markets equilibrate the more inefficiency we
will endure while they do. The second problem is if market participants interpret changes in prices as signals about further changes in prices it is unlikely they
will obey the "laws" of supply and demand. If I believe that even though the price of apples just rose, any further change in the price of
apples is just as likely to be down as up, that is, if I do not interpret the rise in price as a signal that the price is rising, I will probably
demand fewer apples at the new higher price as the law of demand predicts. But if I think that because the price just rose it is more likely
to go up than down the next time it changes, I should buy more apples now that I think the chances are greater than I thought before that
the price of apples will rise. If I want apples I should buy more apples now before they become even more expensive later. And even if I
don't want apples, I should buy more now and sell them tomorrow when the price is even higher. Similarly, if sellers in a market interpret
price changes as signals of what direction prices are headed in, they should offer to sell more when the price falls and sell less when it
rises, the law of supply notwithstanding. 5 In this case, when actual buyers 'behavior is represented by an upward sloping demand curve
and actual sellers' behavior is represented by a downward sloping supply curve, self-interested behavior on the part of frustrated buyers
when there is excess demand will raise a price that is higher than the equilibrium price, not lower it. And self-interested behavior on the
part of frustrated sellers will lower a price that is lower than the equilibrium price, not raise it. In other words, there will be
disequilibrating forces in the market pushing it farther away from equilibrium, not toward it. Conclusion: market failure is significant
While political economists criticize market inefficiencies and inequities, many others have complained, in one way or another, that markets are socially destructive. In effect markets say to us: You cannot consciously coordinate your economic activities efficiently, so don't even try. You cannot come to efficient and equitable agreements among yourselves, so don't even try. Just thank your lucky stars yourselves can still benefit from a division of labor thanks to the miracle of the market system. Markets are a decision to punt in the game of human economic relations, a no confidence vote on the social capacities of the human species. Samuel Bowles explained markets' antisocial bias eloquently in an essay titled "What Markets Can and Cannot Do" published in Challenge Magazine in July 1991. Even if market allocations did yield Pareto-optimal results, and even if the resulting income distribution was thought to be fair (two very big "ifs"), the market would still fail if it supported an undemocratic structure of power or if it rewarded greed, opportunism, political passivity, and indifference toward others.
The central idea here is that our evaluation of markets - and with it the concept of market failure - must be expanded to include the effects of markets on both the structure of power and the process of human development. As anthropologists have long stressed, how we regulate our exchanges and coordinate our disparate economic activities influences what kind of people we become. Markets may be considered to be social settings that foster specific types of personal development and penalize others ... The beauty of the market, some would say, is precisely this: It works well even if people are indifferent toward one another. And it does not require complex communication or even trust among its participants. But that is also the problem. The economy - its markets, work places and other sites - is a gigantic school. Its rewards encourage the development of particular skills and attitudes while other potentials lay fallow or atrophy. We learn to function in",. these environments, and in so doing become someone we might not have become in a different setting ... By economizing on valuable traits - feelings of solidarity with others, the ability to empathize, the capacity for complex communication and collective decision making, for example - markets are said to cope -with the scarcity of these worthy traits. But in the long run markets contribute to their erosion and even disappearance. What looked like a hardheaded adaptation to the infirmity of human nature may in fact be part of the problem. Markets and hierarchical decision making economize on the use of valuable but scarce human traits like "feelings of solidarity with
others, the ability to empathize, the capacity for complex communication and collective decision making." But more importantly, markets
and hierarchical relations contribute to the erosion and disappearance of these worthy traits by rewarding those who ignore democratic
and social considerations and penalizing those who try to take them into account. It is no accident that despite a monumental increase in
education levels, the work force is less capable of exercising its self-management potential at the end of the twentieth century than it was
at the beginning, or that people feel more alone, alienated, suspicious of one another, and rootless than ever before. Robert Bellah, Jean
Bethke Elshtain, and Robert Putnam among others have documented the general decay of civic life and weakening of trust and
participation across all income and educational levels in the United States. There is no longer any doubt that "the social fabric is
becoming visibly thinner, we don't trust one another as much, and we don't know one another as much" in Putnam's words.6 While it is
easier to blame the spread of television than a major economic institution, the atomizing effect of markets as they spread into more and
more areas of our lives bears a major responsibility for this trend. Market prices are systematically biased against social activities in favor of individual activities. Markets make it easier to pursue well
being through individual rather than social activity by minimizing the transaction costs associated with the former and maximizing the
transaction costs associated with the latter. Private consumption faces no obstacles in market economies where joint, or social consumption runs smack into the free rider problem. Markets harness our creative capacities and energy by arranging for other people to
threaten our livelihoods. Markets bribe us with the lure of luxury beyond what others can have and beyond what we know we deserve.
Markets reward those who are the most efficient at taking advantage of his or her fellow man or woman, and penalize those who insist,
illogically, on pursuing the golden rule - do unto others as you would have them do unto you. A mathematics instructor at a small college
in Liaoyang China who had doubled his income running a small fleet of taxis summarized his experience with marketization as follows:
"It's really survival of the fittest here. If you have a cutthroat heart, you can make it. If you are a good person, I don't think you can." 7
Of course, we are told we can personally benefit in a market system by being of service to others. But we know we can often benefit more easily
by tricking others. Mutual concern, empathy, and solidarity are the appendices of human capacities and emotions in market economies - and like
the appendix, they continue to atrophy as people respond sensibly to the rule of the marketplace - do others in before they do you in.
The elasticity of supply and demand allows us to predict how much the supply and demand for goods will change when their price changes.
Elasticity also holds the key to how revenues of sellers will be affected by changes in supply. For example, the demand for corn is usually elastic.
So when a drought hits the corn belt the price will rise and the equilibrium quantity bought and sold will fall. But the percentage fall in sales will
be greater than the percentage increase in price because demand for corn is elastic. Since the revenue of corn farmers is simply equal to the
market price times the quantity sold, the fact that sales drop by a greater percent than the increase in price means revenues must fall. On the
other hand, the demand for oil is usually inelastic. So if war breaks out in the Middle East and a country such as Iraq, Kuwait, Iran, Libya, or
Saudi Arabia is temporarily eliminated as a potential supplier the price will rise and the equilibrium quantity bought and sold will fall as before.
But because demand for oil is inelastic the percentage fall in sales will be less than the percentage increase in price. In this case the revenue of oil
suppliers will increase because the rise in price outweighs the drop in sales when supply decreases.
THE DREAM OF A BENEFICENT INVISIBLE HAND
----------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
THE NIGHTMARE OF A MALEVOLENT INVISIBLE FOOT
2. External effects are notoriously hard to measure in market economies. This is of great significance since their magnitude is critical to
how inefficient a market will be, and how large a pollution tax needs to be to correct the inefficiency. In a 1998 report the Center for
Technology Assessment estimated that when external effects are taken into account the true social cost of a gallon of gasoline consumed
in the US may be as high as $15. 1 just paid $1.02 a gallon when I filled my car up today in southern Maryland. The $1.02 already
includes some hefty taxes, but obviously they are not nearly hefty enough!
---------------------------------------------------------------
--------------------------------------------
Snowballing inefficiency
-------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
---------------------------------------------------------------
---------------------------------------------
5. Mainstream texts persist in treating such behavior as if it was not the obvious violation of the "laws" of supply and demand that it clearly is. Instead of admitting that demand is not always negatively related to market price, and supply is not always positively related to market price, mainstream texts resort to the subterfuge of saying that the change in expectations about the likely direction of future price changes shifts demand curves and supply curves that still do obey the laws of supply and demand, yielding actual results that contradict what those laws lead us to expect. This is sophistry at its
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
A rising price that becomes, at least temporarily, a self-fulfilling prophesy is commonly called a market "bubble," and a falling price
that becomes a self-fulfilling prophesy is often called a market "crash." As we will discover in chapter 7 where we study banks and
international finance, this kind of disequilibrating dynamic occurs more often than market enthusiasts like to admit, particularly in
financial and foreign exchange markets, with disastrous effects on real economies, i.e. on employment, investment, production and
consumption. Finally, there can be a different kind of disequilibrating dynamic that operates between markets that are connected in a
particular way. When one market is initially out of equilibrium it can cause another market to fall out of equilibrium. When this second
market falls out of equilibrium it can push the first market even farther away from equilibrium, which in turn pushes the second market farther out of equilibrium as well. The result can be a "vicious" interaction in which each market pushes the other farther
away from its equilibrium, and it is possible for this disequilibrating force to be stronger than the equilibrating forces of price
adjustments within markets described in the micro law of supply and depand. In chapter 6 on macro economics we focus on how the
market for labor and the market for goods in general interact. One of Keynes' greatest insights was his discovery that disequilibrating dynamics that operate between goods and labor markets can push both markets farther away from their equilibrium faster than price and wage adjustments within them push them toward equilibrium. This insight allowed Keynes to explain why production and employment keep dropping in a depression even though there are more and more workers willing to work - if only someone would hire them and plenty of employers anxious to produce goods - if only someone would buy them.
In sum, convenient deals with mutual benefits for buyer and seller should not be confused with economic efficiency. When some kinds of preferences are consistently under-represented because of transaction cost and free rider problems, when consumers adjust their preferences to biases in the market price system and thereby aggravate those biases, and when profits can be increased as often by externalizing costs onto parties external to market exchanges as from productive behavior, theory predicts that free market exchange will often result in a misallocation of scarce productive resources. Theory tells us free market economies will allocate too much of society's resources to goods whose production or consumption entail negative external effects, and too little to goods whose production orconsumption entail positive external effects, and there is every reason to believe the misallocations are significant. When markets are less than perfectly competitive - which they almost always are -and fail to equilibrate instantaneously - which they always do - the results are that much worse.
MARKETS UNDERMINE THE TIES THAT BIND US
------------------------------------
---------------------------------------------------------------------
6.Putnam made this remark when interviewed at the 1995 annual meeting of the American Association of Political Scientists in Chicago (Washington Post,
September 3, 1995: A5).
7. Reported in "With Carrots and Sticks, China Quiets Protesters," Washington Post, March 22, 2002: A. John Pomfret covered the downside of China's conversion to a capitalist economy in a series of eye opening articles published in the Washington Post during March 2002. Most whom Pomfret interviewed protesting layoffs, lost back pay, and rampant corruption declined to be identified by name, knowing this would almost surely lead to their arrest. Pomfret ended the above article with a quote from a rare exception. Wang Bing offered the following assessment of China's conversion to capitalism: "They say the country is heading in the right direction. Maybe. But for the average guy here, things are definitely getting worse. The workers used to be the masters of this country. What are we the masters of now?"